1. Overture
Learning a new science involves learning not only the formal
contents of that science but also the particular worldview shared
by the people who practice that science. The formal contents
of physiological psychology have been systematized in various
textbooks, some of which are listed in Table 1. On the other
hand, academic education in physiological psychology has almost
always neglected the description of the worldview shared by physiological
psychologists. This is an unfortunate situation, as the scientific
Weltanschauung, or esprit scientifique, is an essential part
of the education of any scientist.
The description of the worldview of a particular science has
traditionally been the job of philosophers of science. This
book describes the worldview of physiological psychology and,
therefore, is entitled Philosophy of physiological psychology.
As it will be evident shortly, my intent is to be descriptive
rather than prescriptive. Therefore, my handling of physiological
psychology does not resemble Hoyle's (1984) handling of neuroethology,
which understandably generated discontentment in the scientific
community (Bassler 1984, Davis 1984, Simmons 1984).
Before we move into specific issues in the philosophy of physiological
psychology, we must spend some time on the task of defining both
physiological psychology and philosophy of science.
TABLE 1 Some Textbooks on Physiological Psychology |
1. An introduction to physiological psychology, by A. M. Schneider and B. Tarshis (Publisher: Random House) |
2. Biological psychology, by Eugene H. Galluscio (Publisher: MacMillan) |
3. Biological psychology, by James W. Kalat (Publisher: Wadsworth) |
4. Biopsychology, by John P. J. Pinel (Publisher: Allyn and Bacon) |
5. Foundations of physiological psychology, by Richard F. Thompson (Publisher: Harper and Row) |
6. Introduction to biological psychology, by Philip M. Groves and Kurt Schlesinger (Publisher: W. C. Brown) |
7. Introduction to physiological psychology, by Charles F. Levinthal (Publisher: Prentice Hall) |
8. Physiological psychology, by J. Anthony Deutsch and Diana Deutsch (Publisher: Dorsey) |
9. Physiological psychology, by P. M. Milner (Publisher: Holt, Rinehart and Winston) |
10. Physiological psychology, by Mark R. Rosenzweig and Arnold L. Leiman (Publisher: D. C. Heath) |
11. Physiology of behavior, by Neil R. Carlson (Publisher: Allyn and Bacon) |
2. Physiological psychology
Physiological psychology is the science that studies the biological
bases of behavior. For this reason, physiological psychology
is sometimes referred to as biological psychology, biopsychology,
or psychobiology. This means that the physiological psychologist
studies the biological factors (as opposed to economic, social,
or cultural factors) that cause or constitute behavior. Although
the expression biological bases of behavior refers to a large
number of physiological processes, contemporary usage equates
biological bases with neural substrates (Davis et al 1988).
Consequently, physiological psychology today is a synonym of
behavioral neuroscience rather than a synonym of psychobiology
as it used to be in the 1950's. I will not express my opinion
about whether this neuroscience bias is good or bad, nor will
I try to estimate how long the trend will last. Since the president
of the United States designated the 1990's as the "decade of
the brain" (Judd 1989), the neuroscience bias was probably
beneficial to the extent that it improved federal
funding for research in physiological psychology.
A contemporary definition of physiological psychology would
refer, therefore, not to the biological bases of behavior but
to the neural substrates of behavior (including the special class
of behavior called mental activity). The name physiological
psychology has been adopted by numerous authors (e.g., Brown
1976, Deutsch & Deutsch 1973, Isaacson 1971, Morgan & Stellar
1950, Rosenzweig & Leiman 1982, Thompson 1967, Wayner 1971),
although several alternative names have been proposed, such as
biopsychology (Valenstein 1973), psychobiology (Myers 1971),
neuropsychology (Pribram 1954), neurobehavioral science (Isaacson
1973), behavioral neuroscience (Thompson 1983), and others.
In certain instances, names that might seem alternative names
actually designate subspecialties of physiological psychology,
such as neuropsychology (Maher & Maher 1979, Meier 1974), psychophysiology
(Ax 1964, Sternbach 1967), and neuroethology (Camhi 1984, Ewert
1980).
A number of examples and counter-examples of typical experimental
studies will help delineate the boundaries of physiological psychology.
Two of the most vivid examples of the study of the neural basis
of behavior are the evocation of visual and auditory experiences
by electrical stimulation of specific sites on the cerebral cortex
in humans (Penfield 1966) and the evocation of what seems to
be the ultimate sensation of pleasure by stimulation of diencephalic
structures in rats (Routtenberg 1978). On the other hand, the
study of the areas of the brain involved in muscular movements
evoked by electrical stimulation of the motor cortex (Collins
et al 1986) would belong to neurology or neurophysiology rather
than physiological psychology, since only the neural component
(and not the behavioral one) is being investigated. Analogously,
the evocation of thermoregulatory behavior by thermal stimulation
of the hypothalamus (Refinetti & Carlisle 1986, Satinoff 1964)
belongs to physiological psychology, whereas the study of electrophysiological
characteristics of thermal receptors in the brain (Barker & Carpenter
1970, Kelso et al 1982) does not. Naturally, this distinction
implies no attribution of scientific merit or of conceptual incommensurability.
Electrophysiology is as scientifically important as physiological
psychology, and an electrophysiological experiment that investigates,
for instance, the firing characteristics of thermal receptors
in the monkey's hand (Darian-Smith et al 1979) is extremely valuable
for physiological psychology if the results are correlated with
results from psychophysical experiments on thermal discrimination
in humans (Johnson et al 1979). The same may be said about the
study of the relationship between the electrical activity of
single neurons in the inferior colliculus of the newborn mouse
(Shnerson & Willott 1979) and the ability of these animals to
respond to acoustic stimuli (Shnerson & Willott 1980).
Many additional examples may be given. The mapping of brain
regions that are active during ingestive behavior (Hall 1989)
and the inhibition of ingestive behavior by infusion of nutrients
directly into the rat brain (Davis et al 1981) are examples of
research in physiological psychology. On the other hand, the
study of the effects of changes in taste and nutrient content
of food on ingestive behavior in humans (Rolls et al 1988) and
the study of how taste aversion is learned in rats (Garcia &
Koelling 1966) belong to behavioral psychology or regulatory
physiology rather than to physiological psychology, since only
the behavioral component (and not the neural one) is being investigated.
Analogously, the investigation of the effects of cerebellar
lesions on emotional behavior in rats (Supple et al 1987), or
of cortical lesions on sensory discrimination (Finger et al 1970),
or of hippocampal lesions on memory (Jagielo et al 1990), or
of cortical lesions on learning capability (Brennan 1979, Gabriel
et al 1979), or of hypothalamic lesions on thermoregulatory behavior
(Refinetti & Carlisle 1987) are all examples of research in physiological
psychology. On the other hand, the study of the sensory determinants
of suckling behavior in weanling rats (Bruno et al 1980), or
of social relations among non-human primates (Harcourt 1979,
Sade 1967), or of the punishment procedure in operant conditioning
(Azrin & Holz 1966), or of the behavioral thermal preference
of the rat (Refinetti & Horvath 1989) belong to behavioral psychology
and ethology rather than to physiological psychology. As before,
this distinction implies no attribution of scientific merit or
of conceptual incommensurability. Purely behavioral studies
are just as important as studies that examine the neural correlates
of behavior. In fact, physiological psychology, behavioral psychology,
neurophysiology, and regulatory physiology are all interrelated
sciences. Except for the few exceptions described later on in
this book, all of these sciences contribute to the advancement
of our knowledge of how the animal body (including the brain)
performs the various tasks required for the survival of the individual
and the species and for the enjoyment of human existence.
3. Philosophy of science
Philosophy of science is the study of how science goes about
its own business, that is, how science obtains knowledge. If
there is one thing everyone agrees on, it is that knowledge is
not given a priori. In other words, knowledge must be obtained
gradually. How knowledge is obtained, and even what knowledge
really is, remains controversial. This controversial situation
should not be too disturbing, however. After all, if we do not
expect science to be a finished enterprise (where everything
to be known is already known), we should not expect philosophy
of science to be a finished enterprise either. One aspect of
scientific activity that all philosophers of science seem to
agree on is the dialectical nature of scientific knowledge.
In other words, it seems clear that scientists are in a constant
swing between adherence to rules of proper scientific conduct
(i.e., methodologies, theories, hypothesis, etc.) and the rejection
of these same rules to adopt new ideas.
In the 19th century, Wilhelm Hegel was probably the first philosopher
to formally express the idea of a dialectical progression of
knowledge. In Hegel's conception, not only science but all human
experience progresses by solving conflicts between a previously
established thesis and a new thesis (the antithesis) in such
a way that a third thesis results which is closer to the absolute
truth than either of the two previous formulations (Hegel 1931,
1964). The dialectical process is especially clear when traditional
dichotomies are involved (such as nature-nurture, conformism-revolution,
etc), but it can also be seen in more common situations such
as the synthesis of communism and liberalism into the democracies
of the late 20th century. It should be mentioned in passing
that the dualistic logic of our civilization (which makes the
dialectical process possible) has been criticized as an unworthy
result of the Judaico-Christian heritage of moral impotency (Nietzsche
1918) or of the patriarchal nature of our societies (Bleier 1984).
Whether these criticisms are correct or not, the fact remains
that science as we know it progresses according to a dialectical
process. Hegel's conception of a perfect totalization of knowledge
at each step of the process may be flawed (Refinetti 1989), but
the idea of progress as a continuous process of refutation and
elaboration of previous assumptions is almost intuitive.
In the 20th century, Thomas Kuhn saw the dialectical process
as a dynamic balance between normal science and periods of scientific
revolution. During normal science, scientists are carefully
trained according to prevailing rules of scientific conduct and
perform their work in accordance with these rules, whereas the
rejection of part or all of the previous rules characterizes
a scientific revolution (Kuhn 1962). In an attempt to emphasize
the importance of innovative spurts in the scientific endeavor,
Paul Feyerabend suggested that a central component of progressive
research is the acceptance (at the heuristic level) of every
conceivable idea, even though (actually, preferably if) they
have no scientific basis (Feyerabend 1975). Gaston Bachelard
proposed that science could be characterized as a progressive
enterprise that is constantly retarded by a number of epistemological
obstacles (Bachelard 1938). Bachelard's perspective is very
interesting because it avoids the centuries-old problem of deciding
what is right and what is wrong in our knowledge of the world.
It avoids the problem by giving up philosophical arrogance.
Let's examine this matter in more detail.
The activity of gaining knowledge, which we call science today,
used to be called philosophy millennia ago. As more and more
disciplines branched out of philosophy, philosophy overtly maintained
its gnosiologic goals well into the 19th century (Husserl 1965).
That is, both science and philosophy claimed to obtain knowledge,
although the objects of study were different in most cases.
Naturally, philosophy of science was assumed to produce knowledge
about scientific knowledge. For many years, however, philosophers
seemed unable to treat science as a serious object of study.
Although highly sophisticated analyses of scientific investigation
were produced (e.g., Nagel 1961, Popper 1959), philosophers maintained
an unjustified paternalistic attitude all along. For centuries,
the philosopher believed to be able to see deeper than the scientist
and, therefore, to tell the scientist how to behave. In the
16th century, Descartes prescribed general rules of thought that
the scientist should follow in order to obtain knowledge (Descartes
1947). In the 20th century, Carnap believed he could extract
fundamental principles from the physical sciences and prescribe
them to every other branch of science (Carnap 1966). The most
recent attempt to prescribe scientific conduct is probably Laudan's
normative naturalism. He tries to convince us first that philosophy
is a science and, then, to make us believe that empirical science
is only descriptive but philosophy can be both descriptive and
normative and can dictate rules to empirical science (Laudan
1990). Many other philosophers of science with prescriptive
intentions are described by Losee in his interesting book about
the relationship between history of science and philosophy of
science (Losee 1987).
This type of philosophical arrogance found in Descartes, Carnap,
Laudan, and many others is not found in Bachelard. His idea
is that if we are going to study how science obtains knowledge,
then we should let science speak for itself instead of telling
science how to behave. As Gerard Lebrun wisely noted, the first
condition for performing good epistemology (i.e., the study of
knowledge) is the unconditional respect for science (Lebrun 1977).
It does not matter whether science holds the ultimate, absolute
truth about the world; it does hold the best truth we have at
the moment. This faith in science as the possessor of the truth
may seem old-fashioned, but it is actually very much in tune
with the current relativist mood. In the late 19th century,
Auguste Comte generated a long-lasting optimism about the power
of science with his positivist philosophy (Comte 1877), and in
the first half of the 20th century logical empiricism brought
the positivist ideal to its highest level of sofistication (Ayer
1959). Since then, concern has been expressed about the legitimacy
of some assumptions of the positivist philosophy that are now
part of science, especially that of the logical supremacy of
empiricism and the idea of objectivity that goes with it (e.g.,
Longino 1990, Polanyi 1962, Unger 1984). This "relativization"
of science is intellectually exciting but should not obscure
the fact that the study of science must be objective. That is,
although the cultural philosopher is expected to evaluate the
cultural significance and legitimacy of science, the philosopher
of science should not care whether an empiricist attitude is
good or bad, legitimate or arbitrary. Our faith in science is
an acknowledgement of the existence of an institution called
science, independently of what cultural factors contribute to
the establishment and maitenance of this institution. Science
today is empiricist (to a limited but definite extent), and this
is what matters. More than that, as science is a potent source
of knowledge in our days, what hurts science hurts knowledge.
This means that an obstacle to science is a true epistemological
obstacle. It also means that a normative philosophy of science
is just one of many obstacles to science.
A total of 14 epistemological obstacles to the progress of physiological
psychology are described in this book, namely: inflexible realism,
spiritualism, naive humanism, epistemological holism, antivivisectionism,
sociologism, anti-empiricism, organicism, mentalism, psychophysical
complementarism, bidimensionalism, innatism, environmentalism,
and clinical pragmatism. Some of these obstacles are specific
to physiological psychology, whereas others affect the whole
of psychology, and some threaten science in general.
In addition to the deleterious effects of epistemological obstacles,
physiological psychology may have its progress obstructed also
by factors of a different nature. In a broad sense, anything
that reduces the time invested in research on physiological psychology
constitutes an obstacle. Thus, a physiological psychologist
interested in biological rhythms would be productive by studying
the changes in brain metabolism that accompany circadian changes
in locomotor activity (Room & Tielemans 1989) but would be obstructive
by studying the cellular neurophysiology of isolated central
pattern generators (e.g., Lydic 1989) because physiological psychology
time would be "wasted" on pure neurophysiology. Naturally, this
type of obstacle has little relevance. The scientist who leaves
the laboratory earlier to avoid rush-hour traffic on the way
home would generate an equivalent obstacle. Time is certainly
an important commodity in our days, but it would be frivolous
to point out that goofing off is an obstacle to the advancement
of science. Therefore, we may consider for practical purposes
that only epistemological obstacles are intellectually meaningful
obstacles. A physiological psychologist who occasionally conducts
pure neurophysiological research is a person with multiple interests
and not an obstructor of the progress of physiological psychology.
4. This book
It should be clear by now that this book's arguments are based
on two main principles, as follows: 1) the education of a physiological
psychologist should include not only the methodological and conceptual
body of knowledge of physiological psychology but also the worldview
shared by the physiological psychology community of scientists;
and 2) because philosophy of science cannot legitimize its aspiration
to be normative, it can only be helpful to science (and, consequently,
to society in general) if it fosters the analysis of epistemological
obstacles that jeopardize the progress of scientific research.
Consequently, the study of the epistemological obstacles to
the advancement of physiological psychology may be seen as a
contribution to both science education and philosophy of science.
As a contribution to science education, this book should be
useful to undergraduates and graduate students as well as to
professional scientists and educators. Although rote memorization
of the epistemological obstacles described in this book would
serve no purpose, awareness of their existence should prove to
be extremely helpful for those who enter the field of physiological
psychology. Such awareness should have two main consequences:
it should produce a higher likelihood that physiological psychology
will continue to develop freely, and it should stimulate reflection
about one's own personal convictions regarding science and scientific
knowledge. After all, to acquire the worldview of physiological
psychology is to learn how to avoid the epistemological obstacles
that threaten its development. Regarding general scientific
conduct, one may want to read also Merton's short essay on the
normative structure of science, where he suggests that four sets
of moral/technical imperatives (viz., universalism, communism,
disinterestedness, and organized skepticism) comprise the ethos
of a contemporary scientist (Merton 1942).
Still in the context of science education, it should be kept
in mind that the dialectical nature of scientific investigation
forces itself upon my analysis of epistemological obstacles.
Thus, on one hand, the objective of this book is to help prospective
physiological psychologists obtain a solid base in physiological
psychology by adding to their formal education some knowledge
of the worldview of physiological psychology. After all, it
is only through the assimilation of the scientific worldview
and the scientific facts and methodologies that a person becomes
a scientist. On the other hand, progress (which is the major
distinctive characteristic of science) is obtained by refuting
or refining previous knowledge. Consequently, progress is often
due to non-conformists, to students who failed to assimilate
the rules or refused to follow them. This means that I do not
expect any reader to accept every argument in this book. To
the dispair of single-minded educators, the bottom line of science
education ends up being something like this: "You must learn
these rules in order to become a scientist; but if you learn
them too well you will be only a mediocre scientist." A necessary
feature of the dialectical process is that a new synthesis is
obtained at the expense of the denial of a previous thesis.
As a contribution to philosophy of science, this book has obviously
modest goals. For one, no special effort was made to produce
an exhaustive list of epistemological obstacles to the development
of physiological psychology. Also, other important topics in
the philosophy of a science (such as the rigorous description
of the ontological lexicon employed by that science, or the detailed
analysis of the mechanisms responsible for the generation of
new ideas and assimilation of unpredicted discoveries) were not
addressed at all in this book. Finally, no attempt was made
to evaluate the applicability of the principles found in physiological
psychology to other life sciences or other experimental sciences
in general. The limited scope of the book may turn out to be
its major asset, however. A concise, well-focused monograph
is less likely to contain unjustified generalizations and more
likely to attract the attention of busy readers who cannot afford
to dedicate too many hours to any single book.